YIPPOCAMPUS, VOL. 1, NO. 3, PAGES 230-235, JULY 1991

An Allocentric Spatial Model for the Hippocampal Cognitive Map John O’Keefe Anatomy and D e v e l o p m e n t a l Biology, University College L o n d o n , Gower S t r e e t , London WC1 E 6BT, U.K. SPATIAL BEHAVIORS VS. SPATIAL NEURAL SYSTEMS The term “spatial behavior” is ambiguous and needs to be clarified. It might mean behaviors that can best be described with reference to a spatial reference framework. o r it might mean behaviors that are dependent on spatial neural systems. An example of the first is the demonstration by Golani (1976) that the seemingly complcx movements which form the social interaction between two jackals can be described in several different frameworks, including the use of a framework centered on one animal to describe the movements of the other. Other aspects of behavior will best be described with reference to egocentric frameworks centered on the eye, head or body axis, or axes centered on individual objects or environmental frameworks. It might transpire. however, that the neural systems that generate these behaviors are not in themselves spatial systems, but are acting according to nonspatial principles that conspire with the environment to produce “spatial” behavior. For example, the behavior of an animal approaching a light might best be described as reducing the linear distance between the animal and the object, but might in fact be subserved by systems operating on the principle “increase the intensity of the light,” resulting in the animal’s moving up an intensity gradient (Barto and Sutton. 1981). Similarly, as the behaviorists realized. even complex spatial behaviors such as maze learning could, in principle, be dependent on chains of simple associations between stimuli and responses (see stimulus A , activate muscle sequence I; see stimulus B, activate muscle sequence 11, etc.). An example of the way in which a “nonspatial” hippocampus might support spatial behavior is the stimulus-response associationist model proposed by McNaughton (1988) and McNaughton and Nadel (1989). In this model the activity of the hippocampal complex-spike cells represents the sensory view from a location; the role of the hippocampus is to associate this view with a particular movement (e.g., turn left) in order to predict the subsequent local view. The power to generate novel behaviors on the basis of such a system depends on the ability to string together stimulus-response-stimulus components and to generate motor equivalences, such as two left turns are equivalent to an about-face in extrahippocampal areas like the parietal cortex. N o spatial system is needed. The second meaning of spatial behavior is behavior generated by information stored in an explicitly spatial system. The strong claims of the cognitive map theory are that one such spatial system represents environments within an allo-

centric spatial framework, that the ordering principles of thc system are the Euclidean distance and direction between places within that framework, and that the system is localized within the nervous system to the hippocampal region. The role of this hippocampal place system in “spatial” behavior and “spatial” tasks is not straightforward and require.; a detailed analysis of each task o r behavior in terms of the possible strategies or hypotheses that might underpin it anti the environmental manipulations that would either force the animal to select one hypothesis or, alternatively, enable the experimenter to identify which of several possible hypotheses an animal was actually using. Lynn Nadel and 1 devoted considerable space in our review of the lesion literature to this task, but misunderstanding still persists. For example, the Olton radial arm maze (Olton and Samuelson, 1976) and the Morris water maze task (Morris, 1981) are considered to be “spatial” tasks, and even partial success on either by hippocampal animals is counted against the cognitive map theory. Yet they both can be solved by non-place strategies depending on the particular configuration and procedure used. The usual version of the Morris task has distinct advantages over the Olton maLe in that direction hypotheses can be used to solve the latter but are not very efficient in the water tank since the animal is started from several locations and must approach the goal from a different direction on different trials. The water maze can. however, be solved by a nonhippocarnpal guidance strategy if there is a prominent cue outside the pool behind the goal and the animal is started from the same location on every trial. In this case, use of a guidance strategy would be demonstrated by relocation or removal of the cue once the animals had learned. Eichenbaum et al. (1990) have recently demonstrated guidance learning in the water maze by placing black curtains and a relay rack behind the goal and starting the animals from the same location on each trial. Probe trials confirmed the vital role of the cues in guiding behavior. Damage to the hippocampal system had minimal effect as predicted by the cognitive map theory. Surprisingly, the authors misinterpreted these results as showing that the lesioned animals had demonstrated place learning and concluded that they counted against the cognitivc map theory! I would like to suggest that the use of the ambiguous terms “spatial behavior.” “spatial learning.” and “spatial task” be discontinued and that, in future, predictions about the behavioral effects of hippocampal lesions be derived in the manner that Nadel and I advocated and that 1 have outlined above. In particular, they should be derived from theories that have as their core a model that can be related to the anatomy and physiology of the hippocampal system. I am convinced that, without such a constraint, the cognitive map, as with so many ideas in this field, reduces to just one more vague notion that each player is free to interpret in his o r her own way, and over which endless semantic battles can be fought. In the remainder of this article I will sketch out one version of such a computational model.

HIPPOCAMPAL UNITS A N D THE M A P MODEL As Lynn Nadel mentioned in the target article, the genesis of the cognitive map theory was the discovery of the spatial cells of the hippocampus in freely moving rats (O’Keefe and Dostrovsky, 1971). In addition, however. many of the prop-

ALLOCENTRIC SPATIAL MODEL / O’Keefe

231

erties attributed to the cognitive mapping system were de- derived from several unit observations. Primary amongst rived from the properties of these and other cell types in the these was the existence of misplace cells, which signaled the hippocampus. Three types of cells were described: place absence of expected items or the presence of unexpected cells, displace cells, and misplace cells. These three classes items in a particular place (O’Keefe, 1976). Furthermore, of neurons had comparable counterparts in cell types de- place cells could be found in nongoal areas of an environment scribed by Ranck (1973) in his coeval study, although he did or, indeed, in environments entirely bereft of rewards and not emphasize their spatial characteristics. The early non- punishments. Recently, we (Speakman and O’Keefe, 1990) computational models (Nadel and O’Keefe, 1974; O’Keefe have strengthened this postulate of a cognitive motivation by and Nadel, 1974) were based on the assumption that each showing that relocating the reward in a +-maze task had no place cell represented a patch of an environment and that effect on the fields of almost all of the hippocampal place these patches were connected together by the displace cells, cells recorded during the task. which were suggested to code for the distance between places The modifiability of the place cells and their suitability as on the basis of the animal’s movements. The notion of places memory elements was first suggested by the observation that in an allocentric space derived from the observation that al- they changed their response to environmental alterations though some of the place cells had directional firing fields, such as turning the lights off o r rotating the maze. Usually others were omnidirectional, firing equally well rrgavdless of on the very first exposure to the change, the place field firing the direction in which the animal faced within the field disappeared, but the cell quickly ‘‘learned’’ to maintain its (O’Keefe, 1976). Further, nondirectional local cues (olfactory field after one o r two experiences of the altered environment. and tactile) could be ruled out as sole determinants of place The responses of these cells to repeated exposure t o the dark field firing by substitution of a different arm for the usual arm. has been examined more extensively by Jones-Leonard et al. This dominance of extramaze over intramaze cues in the con- (1985) and by Quirk et al. (1990). Both found that the cells trol of place firing has been shown repeatedly for elevated maintained their fields if the rat was in the environment when mazes (Kubie and Ranck, 1983: Olton et al., 1978). in contrast the lights were turned off. This ability of these cells to reto enclosed boxes in which intramaze cues predominate member the spatial properties of the environment after a brief (Kubie and Ranck, 1983). The importance of the direction- exposure has been explored in experiments recently pubality correlate for the development of models continues to the lished by Andrew Speakman and myself (O’Keefe and Speakpresent. McNaughton et al. (1983) found that most of the man, 1987). We studied the spatial representation in the hipplace cells were directional when animals were tested on an pocampus of an environment in which we controlled the eight-arm radial maze with narrow arms. Bostock et al. (1988) extramaze spatial cues by rotating them as an ensemble from have confirmed this but also found that none of the 13 place trial to trial. The rat had to solve a simple place learning task cells tested with the rats in a cylinder had directional fields. on an elevated +-maze where the goal was identified by its McNaughton ( 1988) has suggested that the strength of the constant relationship to these cues. Hippocampal complex directionality factor in the radial maze might mean that the spike cellc had place fields that maintained their location relacells are in fact responding to the local view from the field tive to the controlled spatial cues, replicating the previous location: he has proposed a theory of hippocampal function findings of O’Keefe and Conway ( 1978). By exposing the rat based on this finding (see above). In contrast, I prefer to to a particular configuration of cues at the beginning of a trial believe that the directionality of the place field firing depends and then removing them before it was allowed to run to the on the shape of the environment and/or is imposed by the goal arm, we established both that the place cells maintained the appropriate firing fields during this memory period and direction cells in the presubiculum. The notion that there existed a subsystem for changing the that the rat remembered where the goal was at the end of representation within the map from the current location to each trial. This knowledge was usually not revealed in any the next location following a movement derived from the find- aspect of the animal’s behavior in the start arm. The rat aping that the displace cells, like the EEG theta waves (Van- peared to have a map of the cue-controlled environment, derwolf, 1969). were clearly related t o movements but not to which it could orient in four positions relative to the labothe direction of the movement o r the specific muscle groups ratory frame, and which it could maintain following the reinvolved. It was noted that in order to predict the next lo- moval of the spatial cues. Detour trials in which the rat was cation, directional as well as distance information would be forced to go to a nongoal arm during the memory period necessary, and the absence of any pure directional infor- showed that once the appropriate hippocampal representamation in the hippocampal cellular response was considered tion had been set up. it could be continuously updated in the problematic for the mapping theory; the existence of such absence of the controlled cues. Control trials in which the information was predicted (O’Keefe, 1976; O’Keefe and spatial cues were absent throughout the trial showed that the Nadel, 1978). The major discovery of the head direction cells rat still entertained an internally consistent map in a particular by Ranck and his colleagues (Ranck, 1984: Taube et al., 1990) orientation and chose the goal arm that was consistent with in the dorsal presubiculum has removed the last major ob- this map. but that the orientation could change from one constacle in the construction of a computational theory for the trol trial to the next. The rat went where it thought the goal was. That the goal was subordinate to and located within the cognitive map. The idea that learning changes within the mapping system map, and not vice versa, was demonstrated by a subsequent were not driven by biological needs or reinforcers but by mis- experiment (Speakman and O’Keefe, 1989). Here, it was matches between the current sensory inputs and those ex- shown that changing the food location relative to the conpected on the basis of the latest map of that environment trolled cues half-way through the recording period and re-

232

HIPPOCAMPUS VOL. 1, NO. 3, JULY 1991

training the animal to the new goal location did not alter the spatial firing fields of most cells (see Breese et al., 1989 for an alternative view). Experiments in a cylindrical environment in which the fields could be rotated by rotation of a polarizing white card demonstrated identical effects, although it was not possible to test the animal’s knowledge of its environment since there was no explicit goal (Muller et al., 1987; Muller and Kubie, 1987). If anything, it could be presumed that in this latter experiment, as in an earlier experiment by McNaughton et al. (1983) on a forced choice radial arm maze, the rats were not using a place strategy to solve the task. The hippocampus appears to track the animal’s location even when not required to d o so. My recent efforts have been directed toward exploring how the hippocampus might provide an egocentric spatial framework for locating the array of objects within a head-centered framework (O’Keefe, 1988) o r an allocentric framework centered on the environment (O’Keefe. 1990; 1991). I will briefly describe the major components of this latter model and discuss how it addresses some of the claims that have acted as a barrier to acceptance of the cognitive map theory, in particular, the existence of apparently nonspatial correlates of the single unit responses in the hippocampus of awake ani mals and the claim that hippocampal damage affects nonspatial memory.

THE CENTROID MODEL FOR THE HIPPOCAMPAL COGNITIVE MAP THEORY The primary requirements of a spatial system are a coordinate system that serves as a reference framework within which the animal, the objects contained in the environment, and all other places occupied or unoccupied can be located. The model should, in addition, describe the machinery for changing the location of the representation of the animal during movement, for storing the locations of incentives or punishments, and for calculating the translation necessary to get from the current location (or any location) to a desired location. In addition, the model should explain how environmental representations are constructed and changed, and how the correct representation for the current environment is retrieved from all of the previously stored areas. The current model suggests that the allocentric framework is a polar coordinate system whose center is the geometrical center of moments of the cues in the environment (centroid) and whose principal axis is the direction given by a measure of the departure of these cues from a symmetrical distribution (slope). The egocentric representation of cues on which the computations are based is shown in Figure 1A. The centroid is the average of the egocentric vectors from the animal’s current location to each of the cues in the environment (Fig. 1C). The resultant vector identifies a location in the environment that is independent of the animal’s location. The major axis for the allocentric framework is provided by the average slopes between all of the cue pairs in the environment (Fig. 1C). The computation of the slope between each cue pair is performed by subtraction (rather than addition) of their cue vectors. The average of these slopes gives an overall direction that can serve as the second major component of the mapping framework. The calculation of the centroid is attributed to the CA3

pyramidal cells, each of which makes an estimate of the centroid on the basis of the limited subset of cues available to it. These minicentroids form a matrix that uniquely identifies each place in every environment. There are several ways in which the place cells might encode this information. One possibility currently under investigation is that each vector is represented in phasor notation where the length of the vector or distance to the cue is represented by the amplitude of a sine wave, and the angle in egocentric space is represented by the phase of the sine wave relative to a reference (Fig. IB). The theta system is viewed as a compound waveform (Vanderwolf and Leung, 1983), the function of one component being to provide the standard sinusoidal reference wave against which phase angles are measured. Vector addition in such a system is performed by linear summation of the sinusoids. Movements that translate and/or rotate the animal in the environment are also represented as vectors; this information is carried by a second component of the theta system. The direction that serves as the allocentric axis is coded as a matrix of minislopes in the dorsal presubiculum where Ranck and his colleagues (Ranck, 1984; Taube et al., 1990) have reported finding the head-direction cells. I n a fashion analogous to the use of the displacement component of the theta vector to update the location matrix during movement, the current heading direction is updated by rotational movement cues, such as those provided by head angle and joint receptors and the vestibular system. It is assumed that these are converted to the phasor notation and added to the current heading using linear addition. Thus, the system has two independent measures derived from the environment, the direction, which is independent of the animal’s location in the environment, and the location, which is independent of the direction. Together they provide an allocentric reference framework, which fulfills all of the properties of a cognitive map. Some of the criticisms of the theory can be addressed by the centroid model. For example, critics who seek to find a broader function for the hippocampus cite evidence of simple cue responses in hippocampal cells in support. O’Keefe (1976) reported a small number of hippocampal cells with nonspatial sensory responses, including several sniffing units, but chose not to emphasize them. For example, one cell fired when the animal sniffed at its water bowl, while another fired when the rat sniffed at the experimenter’s hand. Eichenbaum et al. (1987) have reported that hippocampal cells fired during sniffing in an olfactory discrimination task and had spatial fields. These sniffing cells may be spatially dependent and, therefore, identical to the misplace cells described above. o r they may in fact be pure olfactory cells, as Eichenbaum et al. suggest. The latter need not mean that the hippocampus has nonspatial as well as spatial functions. One version of the spatial model proposed above suggests that the firing rate of a place cell is an inverse function of the distance to the centroid. In this model, one would expect to find some cells that acted as though they were responding to individual sensory cues. Recall that each hippocampal complex-spike cell calculates an estimate of the centroid of the environment on the basis of the subset of cues available to it. In general, cells will have inputs from more than one cue in an environment

ALLOCENTRIC SPATIAL MODEL / O'Keefe

233

0

A I

I

I +

A

-

+

+

-

Fa

Clock

I

R e f e r e nce

+ B = C

Cue A

RB Cue B I I

I

Vector Average C

A

180

B

B

C Fig. 1 . Calculation of the centroid and slope of an environment on the basis of egocentric cue information. (A) The representation of two cues in an egocentric polar framework centered on the head. Each cue is represented by a vector (A and B), whose lengths RA and RB are related to the distance of the cues and whose angles (a and p) correspond to the angles in the head framework. Averaging of two or more cue vectors yields a vector that points to the geometrical center (centroid) of the cue array. (B) One way in which the vector calculations might be performed in the hippocampal system. In phasor notation, each cue vector can be represented by a sinusoid in which the amplitude of the wave is related to the length of the vector RA, and the phase shift of the wave relative to a clock wave is related to the vector angle (a).The linear average of the sinusoids gives the vector average of the vectors. (C) The centroid and the slope of an environment with 5 cues, A-E. The length of the centroid vector is invariant with rotations by the animal in one location but varies with translations. The angle between the slope and the rat's egocentric axis is invariant with translations but changes with rotations. Together, the centroid and the slope provide the basis for an allocentric coordinate framework.

(c)

234

HZPPOCAMPUS VOL. 1, NO. 3, JULY 1991

and will compute a centroid vector pointing to a location devoid of cues. However, for those neurons that receive inputs from only one cue, the centroid estimate will be identical to the cue location, and the neuron will fire maximally to the cue itself. As the number of cues in an environment is reduced. these sensory responses should become more predominant. Models such as the above should also help to clarify the circumstances under which the hippocampus might become involved in the solution of nonspatial tasks, such as those designed by Olton and his colleagues (Olton and Feustle, 1981: Raphaele and Olton. 1988), in which several enclosed boxes, each containing a different set of cues, are interchanged within a trial so that the location of the boxes relative to the room or to one another is not a possible means to solution. While it is correct to conclude that no overall integrated map of the situation is possible under these circumstances, one cannot rule out the use of the hippocampal system in a reduced capacity if no easier or more efficient strategy is available. Perhaps the animal builds several independent maps, each based on the intrabox cues restricted to one of the boxes, and simply codes for the presence or absence of food in that environment o r the recency of a visit to that environment. A similar comment applies to the configural association ideas of Sutherland and Rudy (1989). They suggest that the hippocampus acts to recognize configurations of cues. Again, a hobbled hippocampus might be able to act in such a capacity in the absence of more natural solutions. I would predict the existence of place fields related to the intrabox cues in these nonspatial environments. My final remarks concern the adequacy of the cognitive map model in explaining the role of the hippocampus in human amnesia. Other contributors to this exercise will undoubtedly marshall arguments in favor of the idea that amnesia is due to damage to a combination of structures in the temporal lobe, as originally suggested by Mishkin (1978). and that the contribution of the right hippocampus to this overall deficit is primarily or entirely spatial (Smith and Milner, 1981 ; 1989). My greater concern is with the apparently nonspatial role of the human left hippocampus. Our original idea of a semantic map (O’Keefe and Nadel. 1978). which uses an essentially spatial framework to organize linguistic entities into narratives. has not generated much attention or comment in the psycholinguistic literature. ‘There are, however. continuing attempts to generate space grammars (Langacker, 1982) based to some extent on the notion that all sentences describe relations in symbolic spaces. For example, Langacker notes that prepositions have a primary meaning that is spatial and derive their secondary symbol meanings from this primary spatial root. While this seems obvious for prepositions such as t o , ( i t , or with, Langacker has even suggested that the use of the preposition b y in passive sentences functions in a quasispatial way in the deep structural representation of those sentences. I believe that the way forward here will also depend on the development of an adequate computational model for the human. Here, one can only speculate on some of the changes that would have to be incorporated into the rat model bejarr it could begin to be applied to the human hippocampus. The idea that the left human hippocampus stores narratives com-

mits one to the notion of a temporal dimension to the maps. In addition, the model will need to incorporate the notion of imagined movement within the mapping space in the absence of physical movement, the concept of an agent a s a map entity that can act in the absence of external forces and that contains its own embedded maps as the wellsprings of action, and the notion of self-reference in which there is a representation of the organism in its own map. The language function of the human left hippocampus needs to be explored within this elaborated version of the cognitive mapping system. On this model, language is the means for transferring information from the speaker’s to the listener’s map.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS The research reported in this article was supported by the Medical Research Council of Britain. References Barto. A . G . . and R. S. Sutton (1981) Landmark learning: An illustration of associative search. B i d . Cybern. 42: 1-8. Bostock, E.. J . Taube, and R. U . Muller (1988) The effects of head orientation on the firing of hippocampal place cells. Soc. Neurosci. Abst. 13:127. Breese. C . R.. K. A. Hampson. and S . A . Ikadwyler (1989) Hippocampal place cells: Stereotypy and plasticity. J. Neurosci. 9: 1097-1 I1I, Eichenbaum. H.. M. Kuperstein. A. Fagan. and J . Nagode (19x7) Cue-sampling and goal-approach correlates of hippocampal unit activity in rats perlormingan odor-discrimination task. J. Neurosci. 7:716-732. Eichenbaum. H . . C . Stewart. and R. G. Morris (1990) Hippocampal representation in place learning. J . Neurosci. 10:3531-3542. Golani. 1. (1976) Homeostatic motor processes in mammalian interin Etholog!. actions: A choreography of display. In Pc~r.cpec~tii~es P. P. G. Bateson and P. H . Klopfer. eds.. V . 2. pp. 69-134. Plenum Press. New York, NY. Jones-1,eonard. B.. B. L. McNaughton. and C. A. Barnes (19x5) 1,ong-term studies of place field interrelationships in dentate ~ Y I I J \ neurons. Soc. Neurosci. Abstr. I I : I108. Kubie. J . L.. and J. B . Ranck (1983) Sensory-behavioral correlates in individual hippocampus neuron\ in three situations: Space and W . Seifert. ed., pp. context. In Ncrirohiology of’ihr Hippoc~urvprc.~. 433-447. Academic Press, London. Langacker. R. (1982) Space grammar. analysability, and the English passive. Language. 58:22-80. McNaughton. B. L. (1988) Neural mechanisms for spatial compu~/ trncl Menial tation and information storage. In N ~ r r r .Cotiriec,tions Corirpcrifrrio/i.s. L. Nadel. L. A . Cooper, P. Culicover. and R. M . Harnish. eds.. pp. 285-350. M I T Press. Cambridge. MA. McNaughton, B. L.. and L. Nadel (1989) Hebb-Marr networks and the neurobiological representation of action in space. In Nrrtroscience, trnd Connec./ionist Theory, M. A . Glick and D. E. Kumelhart. eds.. pp. 1-63, I,. Erlbaum, Hillsdale. NJ. McNaughton. B. L.. C. A . Barnes, and J. O‘Keefe (19x3) The contributions of position, direction and velocity t o single unit activity in the hippocampus of freely-moving rats. Exp. Brain Kes. 52:4149. Mishkin. M . (1978) Memory in monkeys severely impaired by combined but not separate removal of the amygdala and hippocampus. Nature 273:297-8. Morris, R . G. M. (1991)Spatial localization does not require the presence of local cues. Learning and Motivation. 12:239-260. Muller, K . U . . and J. L. Kubie (1987) The effects of changes in the

ALLOCENTRIC SPATIAL MODEL / O'Keefe environment on the spatial firing of hippocampal complex-spike cells. J. Neurosci. 7: 1951-1968. Muller, R. U., J. L. Kubie, and J . B. Ranck Jr. (1987) Spatial firing patterns of hippocampal complex-spike cells in a fixed environment. J. Neurosci. 7:1935-1950. Nadel L.. and J . O'Keefe (1974) The hippocampus in pieces and patches: An essay on modes of explanation in physiological psychology. In Essays on the Nervous System: A Festschr$t,for Prof. J . Z. Young, R. Bellairs and E. G . Gray, eds.. pp. 367-390, Clarendon Press, Oxford, U.K. O'Keefe, J. (1976) Place units in the hippocampus of the freely moving rat. Exp. Neurol. 51:78-109. O'Keefe, J . (1988) Computations the hippocampus might perform. In Neural Connections and Mental Computations, L. Nadel, L. A. Cooper, P. Culicover, and R. M. Harnish, eds., pp. 225-284. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. O'Keefe, J. (1990) A computational theory of the hippocampal cognitive map. In Understanding the Bruin Through the Hippocump u s , J . Storm-Mathisen, J. Zimmer, and 0 . P. Ottersen, eds., Prog. Brain Res. 83:301-312. O'Keefe, J . (1991) The hippocampal map and navigational strategies. In Bruin und Sprrce. J . Paillard. ed., pp. 273-295, Oxford University Press, Oxford, U.K. O'Keefe, J . , and Conway, D. H. (1978) Hippocampal place units in the freely moving rat: Why they fire where they fire. Exp. Brain Res. 31:573-590. O'Keefe, J . , and J. Dostrovsky (1971) The hippocampus as a spatial map: Preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely-moving rat. Brain Res. 34:171-175. O'Keefe, J . , and L. Nadel (1974) Maps in the brain. New Scientist 62:749-51. O'Keefe, J., and L. Nadel (1978) The Hippocampus us (I Cognitive Map, Clarendon Press, Oxford. O'Keefe, J . , and A. Speakman (1987) Single unit activily in the rat hippocampus during a spatial memory task. Exp. Brain Res. 68: I27. Olton, D. S . , and R. J. Samuelson (1976) Remembrance of places passed: Spatial memory in rats. J . Exp. Psychol. [Anim. Behav.] 2:97- I 16.

235

Olton, D. S . , and W. A. Feustle (1981) Hippocampal function required for non-spatial working memory. Exp. Brain Kes. 41:380389. Olton, D. S., M. Branch, and P. Best (1978) Spatial correlates of hippocampus unit activity. Exp. Neurol. 58:387-409. Quirk G . J., R. U. Muller, and J . L. Kubie (1990) The firing of hippocampal place cells in the dark depends on the rat's i-ecent experience. J . Neurosci. 10:2008-2017. Ranck, J . B. Jr. (1973) Studies on single neurons in dorsal hippocampal formation and septum in unrestrained rats. Exp. Neurol. 4 I :461-555. Ranck, J. B. Jr. (1984) Head direction cells in the deep cell layers of dorsal presubiculum in freely-moving rats. Soc. Neurosci. Abstr. 10:599. Raphaele, K. C., and D. S . OIton (1988) Hippocampal and amygdaloid involvement in working memory for nonspatial stimuli. Behav. Neurosci. 102:349-355. Smith, M. L . , and B. Milner (1981) The role of the right hippocampus in the recall of spatial information. Neuropsychologia, 19:781-793. Smith, M. L., and B . Milner (1989) Right hippocampal impairment in the recall of spatial location: Encodingdeficit or rapid forgetting? Neuropsychologia 19:71-81. Speakman, A. S., and O'Keefe, J . (1990) Hippocampal complex spike cells do not change their place fields if the goal is moved within a cue controlled environment. Eur. J . Neurosci. 2:544-555 Sutherland. R. J.. and J . W. Rudy (1989) Configural association theory: The role of the hippocampal formation in learning, memory and amnesia. Psychobiol. 17:129-144. Taube. J. S.. R. U . Muller, and J . B. Ranck Jr. (1990) Head-direction cells recorded from the post-subiculum in freely moving rats. I . Description and quantitative analysis. J . Neurosci. 10:420-435. Vanderwolf, C. H. (l96Y) Hippocampal electrical activity and voluntary movement in the rat. EEG and Clin. Neurophysiology. 26:407-418. Vanderwolf, C. H.. and L. W. S . Leung (1983) Hippocampal rhythmical slow activity: A brief history and the effects of entorhinal lesions and phenycyclindine. In. Neurnbiology q f t h e Hippocampits. W. Seifert. ed.. pp. 275-302. Academic Press. London.

An allocentric spatial model for the hippocampal cognitive map.

YIPPOCAMPUS, VOL. 1, NO. 3, PAGES 230-235, JULY 1991 An Allocentric Spatial Model for the Hippocampal Cognitive Map John O’Keefe Anatomy and D e v e...
643KB Sizes 0 Downloads 0 Views